Existentialism and Absurdism - Thou Art Albert Camus - Nobel Laureate
Existentialism and Absurdism – Thou
Art Albert Camus – Nobel Laureate
Albert Camus (7 November 1913 – 4 January 1960) was a French author, journalist and key philosopher of the 20th century.
When we
discuss about Albert Camus, his contemporaries like Jean-Paul Sartre and Franz
Kafka make a spark through our memory chords.
The trio was the most influential writers of the twentieth century. Albert Camus and Jean-Paul Sartre are known
for existentialism. Albert Camus’
views contributed to the rise of the philosophy known as absurdism. He wrote in
his essay The
Rebel
that his whole life was devoted to opposing the philosophy of nihilism while still
delving deeply into individual freedom. They together find a prominent place in
modern literature and philosophy.
Camus
was awarded the 1957 Nobel Prize for Literature "for his important
literary production, which with clear-sighted earnestness illuminates the
problems of the human conscience in our times". He was the second-youngest recipient of the
Nobel Prize in Literature, after Rudyard Kipling, and the first African-born
writer to receive the award. He is the shortest-lived of any Nobel literature
laureate to date, having died in an automobile accident just over two years
after receiving the award.
Albert
Camus philosophy, quotes and sayings find a prominent place in world history
and his doctrines are internationally renowned.
Throughout his life, Camus spoke out against and
actively opposed totalitarianism in its many forms. Early on, Camus was active within the French
Resistance to the German occupation of France during World War II, even
directing the famous Resistance journal, Combat. On the French
collaboration with Nazi
occupiers he wrote: "Now the only moral value is courage, which is useful
here for judging the puppets and chatterboxes who pretend to speak in the name
of the people." After
liberation, Camus remarked, "This country does not need a Talleyrand, but a Saint-Just." The reality of the bloody postwar tribunals soon changed his mind: Camus
publicly reversed himself and became a lifelong opponent of capital punishment.
Albert Camus was born in Mondovi, Algeria in 1913. His father died one year later, and Camus' mother raised him alone. His mother was impoverished and nearly deaf, so the two of them moved to Camus' grandmother's apartment in the Belcourt section of Algiers, near the Arab Quarter of the city. Camus occupied himself with school and sports, proving to be an excellent student and an admirable competitor. He was tutored by an instructor named Louis Germain at the local school, and in 1923 he passed the lycée entrance exams. He was accepted to the school of philosophy at the University of Algiers, but had to take leave due to a bout with tuberculosis. He recommenced his education in 1930, and financed his time at the university through various odd jobs like working for the Meteorological Institute, selling spare car parts, and private tutoring. He received his diplôme d'études supérieures in 1936, and took his first trip to Europe in the same year under the auspices of improving his health. In 1937 he published his first book, a collection of essays entitled L'Envers et L'endroit.
From
1934 to their divorce in 1936, Camus maintained a short marriage to Simone Hié,
the daughter of a wealthy Opthalmologist. Camus joined the Communist Party in
1934, but his relationship with the party was not an easy one, and would remain
ambivalent throughout his life. Also during his time at university, from
1935-39 Camus, with a group of young left-wing intellectuals, founded the
Théâtre de l'Equipe, or the Workers' Theatre. This group wrote a collective
play called Révolte dans les Asturies, which would constitute Camus'
first experience of writing for theatre. They also produced plays by Malraux,
Synge, Gide and Dostoevski. The theatre company was intended to produce
socialist plays specifically for the audience of Algerian workers.
In
1938 Camus became a journalist for an anti-colonialist newspaper called the
Alger-Republicain. He reported specifically on the state of the Muslims of the
Kabylie region, attracting public notice and finally rousing the Algerian
government to take action. Abridged versions of these articles were published
again much later in Actuelles III (1958).
Camus
left Algiers in 1940 for Paris, hoping to work as a reporter for the leftist
press. This same year the German army invaded France, so he returned to North
Africa. He found a teaching position in Oran, and was married for his second
time to Francine Faure, a mathematics instructor. Camus was a self-proclaimed
pacifist, writing openly against war in Europe, and this put him in danger at
this time due to the political right's rise in power in both France and
Algeria. His stay in Oran was short-lived, as he was "advised" to
leave Algeria in March 1940, having been declared a "threat to national
security".
Camus'
exile began when he traveled back to Paris. He arrived just before the German
army had taken Paris and most of Northern France. What was left of the French
army had become demoralized and was in a poor position to be able to defend the
city. In 1943 Camus joined "Combat," a clandestine resistance cell
and newspaper that had been founded in 1942 for underground intelligence and
sabotage. Camus carried false papers for traveling in occupied territory and
adopted the false identity "Beauchard". He helped by smuggling news
of the war to the Parisian public via copies of the Combat paper. He became its
editor in 1943, and held this position for four years. His articles often
called for action in accordance to strong moral principals, and it was during
this period of his life that he formalized his philosophy: that no matter how
inexplicable existence might be, human life remains sacred. During the occupation
the paper was printed in Lyon, and it moved to Paris after the Liberation in
the summer of 1944. The first Paris edition editorial was written by Camus.
During
the war, Camus published a number of works which have become associated with
his doctrine of the absurd: his idea it is impossible to make rational sense of
one's experience, and human life is made meaningless by mortality. He writes:
"This heart within me I can feel, and I judge that it exists. This world I
can touch, and I likewise judge that it exists. There ends all my knowledge,
and the rest is construction." The novel, The Stranger (1942; Eng.
trans., 1946), has become the quintessential work of fiction of the 20th
century on the theme of the alienated outsider. The Myth of Sysiphysus
(1942; Eng. trans., 1955) is an essay dedicated to the absurd. He also
published two plays consistent with this theme: Cross Purpose (1944,
Eng. trans., 1948) and Caligula (1944, Eng. trans., 1948). Although
Camus is attracted to contemporary nihilism in these works, he became
increasingly more ambivalent in his philosophy towards absurdism. He was not
comfortable with the moral indifference necessarily implied by philosophical
absurdism, and his political history and experiences in occupied France led him
to search for a way to address moral responsibility. He exercised these
thoughts in works like Letters to a German Friend (1945), which is
published with a number of other political essays, in Resistance, Rebellion,
and Death (1960). Part of what makes Camus different from other
existentialists and modern philosophers is his fascination for and acceptance
of contradiction. Life may be meaningless for the individual, he writes,
"but mankind and its societies are larger than one person."
In 1944 Camus' wife gave birth to twins, Catherine and Jean. By this time Camus had become a leading voice for the French working class and social change, even attempting to form his own socialist party (a project that was never actualized). He had finally rejected Marxism, and had to endure criticism from many communist factions.
In 1944 Camus' wife gave birth to twins, Catherine and Jean. By this time Camus had become a leading voice for the French working class and social change, even attempting to form his own socialist party (a project that was never actualized). He had finally rejected Marxism, and had to endure criticism from many communist factions.
In
1949 Camus had a relapse of his tuberculosis, and he locked himself in
seclusion to write. When he recovered in 1951 he published L'Homme Révolté
(The Rebel), a text on artistic, historical, and metaphysical rebellion,
in which he lays out the difference between revolution and revolt. Camus sees
revolt as a peaceful, evolutionary process that requires leadership but not
violence. He criticizes Hegel's work, accusing it of glorifying power and the
state over social morality and ethics, and he accuses Marx of co-opting
Hegelian philosophy to allow "any means to an end". Camus prefers
Mediterranean humanism, a philosophy grounded in nature and moderation, to the
violence and historicism he sees as part and parcel to what he calls the
"Absolutist" philosophies. The attacks on Hegel, Marxism and nihilism
in The Rebel had a profound effect on Camus' peers. The book was
described as intellectual treason by leftist critics, and a review by Francis
Jeanson in Les Temps Modernes accused Camus of being a traitor to the
left. After Camus attempted to defend himself in a letter to the publication,
Jean-Paul Sartre, the editor of Les Temps Modernes at the time,
published an open letter in response that tallied 19 pages. The letter included
personal attacks, and marked the end of the two philosophers' friendship.
Despite his isolation from the French intellectual elite, Camus remained an active advocate for human right, increasing his political activities throughout the 1950s. He began to write for l'Express daily newspaper in 1955, covering the Algerian war. The violence was escalating in Algeria with the arrival of French troops, and Camus saw no hope in ending it. He pleaded, however, for a "civil" truce, which would spare the civilian population from violence and limit it to fighting between troops and rebels. He managed to organize a debate between Muslims and the Front Français, in a public setting, which went without incident, an achievement that earned him the nick-name in Algiers of "Le Colonisateur de Bonne Volonté" or the Well-Meaning Colonialist. He came back into favor with intellectual circles in 1956 with the publication of his novel The Fall. In 1957 he was awarded the Nobel Prize for Literature for his essay Réflexions Sur la Guillotine as an influential work on behalf of human rights.
Throughout his life, Camus continued to work for the theatre, taking on the various roles of actor, director, playwright and translator. The themes of his theatrical work primarily wrest with the human desire for understanding and its conflict with the absurd nature of existence. State of Siege (1948; Eng. trans., 1958) and The Just Assassins (1950; Eng. trans., 1958) are two of his distinctly political plays. He also gained acclaim for his stage adaptations of novels such as William Faulkner's Requiem for a Nun (1956) and Dostoyevsky's The Possessed (1957).
Throughout the 193-0s, Camus broadened his interests. He read the French classics as well as the writers of the day—among them André Gide, Henry de Montherlant, André Malraux—and was a prominent figure among the young left-wing intellectuals of Algiers. For a short period in 1934–35 he was also a member of the Algerian Communist Party. In addition, he wrote, produced, adapted, and acted for the Théâtre du Travail (Workers’ Theatre, later named the Théâtre de l’Équipe), which aimed to bring outstanding plays to working-class audiences. He maintained a deep love of the theatre until his death. Ironically, his plays are the least-admired part of his literary output, although Le Malentendu (Cross Purpose) and Caligula, first produced in 1944 and 1945, respectively, remain landmarks in the Theatre of the Absurd. Two of his most enduring contributions to the theatre may well be his stage adaptations of William Faulkner’s Requiem for a Nun (Requiem pour une nonne; 1956) and Fyodor Dostoyevsky’s The Possessed (Les Possédés; 1959).
In the two years before the outbreak of World War II, Camus
served his apprenticeship as a journalist with Alger-Républicain
in many capacities, including those of leader- (editorial-) writer, subeditor,
political reporter, and book reviewer. He reviewed some of Jean-Paul Sartre’s
early literary works and wrote an important series of articles analyzing social
conditions among the Muslims of the Kabylie region. These
articles, reprinted in abridged form in Actuelles III (1958),
drew attention (15 years in advance) to many of the injustices that led to the
outbreak of the Algerian War in 1954.
Camus took his stand on humanitarian rather than ideological grounds and
continued to see a future role for France in Algeria while not ignoring
colonialist injustices.
He enjoyed the most influence as a journalist
during the final years of the occupation of France and the immediate
post-Liberation period. As editor of the Parisian daily Combat,
the successor of a Resistance newssheet run largely by Camus, he held an
independent left-wing position based on the ideals of justice and
truth and the belief that all political action must have a solid moral basis.
Later, the old-style expediency of both Left and Right brought increasing
disillusion, and in 1947 he severed his connection with Combat.
By now Camus had become a leading literary
figure. L’Étranger (U.S. title, The Stranger;
British title, The Outsider), a brilliant first novel begun before the war and
published in 1942, is a study of 20th-century alienation with a portrait of an
“outsider” condemned to death less for shooting an Arab than for the fact that
he never says more than he genuinely feels and refuses to conform to society’s
demands. The same year saw the publication of an influential philosophical
essay, Le Mythe de Sisyphe (The Myth of Sisyphus),
in which Camus, with considerable sympathy, analyzed contemporary nihilism
and a sense of the “absurd.” He was already seeking a way of overcoming nihilism, and his second
novel, La Peste (1947; The Plague), is a
symbolical account of the fight against an epidemic in Oran by characters whose
importance lies less in the (doubtful) success with which they oppose the
epidemic than in their determined assertion of human dignity and fraternity.
Camus had now moved from his first main concept of the absurd to his other
major idea of moral and metaphysical “rebellion.” He contrasted this latter
ideal with politico-historical revolution in a second long essay, L’Homme révolté
(1951; The Rebel), which
provoked bitter antagonism among Marxist critics and such near-Marxist
theoreticians as Jean-Paul Sartre.
His other major literary works are the technically brilliant novel La Chute (1956)
and a collection of short stories, L’Exil et le royaume (1957; Exile
and the Kingdom). La Chute reveals a preoccupation with Christian
symbolism and contains an ironical and witty exposure of the more complacent
forms of secular humanist morality.
In 1957, at the early age of 44, Camus received
the Nobel Prize for Literature. With characteristic modesty he declared that
had he been a member of the awarding committee his vote would certainly have
gone to André Malraux.
Less than three years later he was killed in an automobile accident.
Assessment
As novelist and playwright, moralist and
political theorist, Albert Camus after World War II became the spokesman of his
own generation and the mentor of the next, not only in France but also in
Europe and eventually the world. His writings, which addressed themselves
mainly to the isolation of man in an alien universe, the estrangement of the
individual from himself, the problem of evil, and the pressing finality of
death, accurately reflected the alienation and
disillusionment of the postwar intellectual. He is remembered, with Sartre, as
a leading practitioner of the existential novel. Though he understood the
nihilism of many of his contemporaries, Camus also argued the necessity of defending
such values as truth, moderation, and justice. In his last works he sketched
the outlines of a liberal humanism that rejected the dogmatic aspects of both
Christianity and Marxism.
I would like to give below some titles of his famous works -
I would like to give below some titles of his famous works -
a. Fiction
The Stranger (1942) – From its cold
opening lines, “Mother died today. Or maybe yesterday; I can’t be sure,” to its
bleak concluding image of a public execution set to take place beneath the
“benign indifference of the universe,” Camus’ first and most famous novel takes
the form of a terse, flat, first-person narrative by its main character
Meursault, a very ordinary young man of unremarkable habits and unemotional
affect who, inexplicably and in an almost absent-minded way, kills an Arab and
then is arrested, tried, convicted, and sentenced to death. The neutral style
of the novel – typical of what the critic Roland Barthes called “writing degree
zero” – serves as a perfect vehicle for the descriptions and commentary of its
anti-hero narrator, the ultimate “outsider” and a person who seems to observe
everything, including his own life, with almost pathological detachment.
The Plague (1947) – Set in the coastal
town of Oran, Camus’ second novel is the story of an outbreak of plague, traced
from its subtle, insidious, unheeded beginnings through its horrible,
all-encompassing, and seemingly inescapable dominion to its eventual climax and
decline, all told from the viewpoint of one of the survivors. Camus made no
effort to conceal the fact that his novel was partly based on and could be
interpreted as an allegory or parable of the rise of Nazism and the nightmare
of the Occupation. However, the plague metaphor is both more complicated and
more flexible than that, extending to signify the Absurd in general as well as
any calamity or disaster that tests the mettle of human beings, their
endurance, solidarity, sense of responsibility, compassion, and will. At the end of the novel, the plague finally
retreats, and the narrator reflects that a time of pestilence teaches “that
there is more to admire in men than to despise.” But he also knows “that the
plague bacillus never dies or disappears for good,” that “the day would come
when, for the bane and the enlightening of men, it would rouse up its rats
again” and send them forth yet once more to spread death and contagion into a
happy and unsuspecting city.
The Fall (1956) – Camus’ third novel,
and the last to be published during his lifetime, is, in effect, an extended
dramatic monologue spoken by M. Jean-Baptiste Clamence, a dissipated, cynical,
former Parisian attorney (who now calls himself a “judge-penitent”) to an
unnamed auditor (and thus indirectly to the reader). Set in a seedy bar amid
the night-life of Amsterdam, the work is a small masterpiece of compression and
style: a confessional (and semi-autobiographical) novel, an arresting character
study and psychological portrait, and at the same time a wide-ranging
philosophical discourse on guilt and innocence, expiation and punishment, good
and evil.
b. Drama
Caligula (1938, first produced 1945). “Men die and are not happy” – such is the complaint against the universe pronounced by the young emperor Caligula, who in Camus’ play is less the murderous lunatic, slave to incest, narcissist and megalomaniac of Roman history than a theatrical martyr-hero of the Absurd, a man who carries his philosophical quarrel with the meaninglessness of human existence to a kind of fanatical but logical extreme. Camus himself described his hero as a man “obsessed with the impossible” and willing to pervert all values and if necessary destroy himself and all those around him in the pursuit of absolute liberty. Caligula was Camus’ first attempt at portraying a figure in absolute defiance of the Absurd, and through three revisions of the play over a period of several years he eventually achieved a remarkable composite by adding touches of Sade, of revolutionary nihilism, of the Nietzschean Superman, of his own version of Sisyphus, and even of Mussolini and Hitler, to his original portrait.
c. Essays, Letters, Prose Collections, Articles, and Reviews
Betwixt and Between (1937) – This short
collection of semi-autobiographical, semi-fictional, philosophical pieces might
be dismissed as juvenilia and largely ignored if it were not for the fact that
it represents Camus’ first attempt to formulate a coherent life-outlook and
world-view. The collection, which in a way serves as a germ or starting point
for the author’s later philosophy, consists of five lyrical essays. In
“L’Ironie” (“Irony”), a reflection on youth and age, Camus asserts, in the
manner of a young disciple of Pascal, our essential solitariness in life and
death. In “Entre Oui et Non” (“Between yes and no”) he suggests that to hope is
as empty and as pointless as to despair. Yet he goes beyond nihilism by
positing a fundamental value to existence-in-the-world. In “La Mort dans l’ame”
(Death in the soul”) he supplies a sort of existential travel review,
contrasting his impressions of central and eastern Europe (which he views as
purgatorial and morgue-like) with the more spontaneous life of Italy and
Mediterranean culture. The piece thus affirms the author’s lifelong preference
for the color and vitality of the Mediterranean world, and especially North
Africa, as opposed to what he perceives as the soulless cold-heartedness of
modern Europe. In “Amour de vivre” (“Love of life”) he claims there can be no
love of life without despair of life and thus largely re-asserts the
essentially tragic, ancient Greek view that the very beauty of human existence
is largely contingent upon its brevity and fragility. The concluding essay,
“L’Envers et l’endroit” (“Betwixt and between”), summarizes and re-emphasizes
the basically Romantic themes of the collection as a whole: our fundamental
“aloneness,” the importance of imagination and openness to experience, the
imperative to “live as if . . . .”
Noces (Nuptials) (1938) – This
collection of four rhapsodic narratives supplements and amplifies the youthful
philosophy expressed in Betwixt and Between. That joy is necessarily
intertwined with despair, that the shortness of life confers a premium on
intense experience, and that the world is both beautiful and violent – these
are once again Camus’ principal themes. “Summer in Algiers,” which is probably
the best (and best-known) of the essays in the collection, is a lyrical, at
times almost ecstatic, celebration of sea, sun, and the North African
landscape. Affirming a defiantly atheistic creed, Camus concludes with one of
the core ideas of his philosophy: “if there is a sin against life, it consists
not so much in despairing as in hoping for another life and in eluding the
implacable grandeur of this one.”
The Myth of Sisyphus (1943) – If there
is a single non-fiction work that can be considered an essential or fundamental
statement of Camus’ philosophy, it is this extended essay on the ethics of
suicide (eventually translated and repackaged for American publication in
1955). For it is here that Camus formally introduces and fully articulates his
most famous idea, the concept of the Absurd, and his equally famous image of
life as a Sisyphean struggle. From its provocative opening sentence (“There is
but one truly serious philosophical problem, and that is suicide”) to its
stirring, paradoxical conclusion (“The struggle itself toward the heights is
enough to fill a man’s heart. One must imagine Sisyphus happy”), the book has
something interesting and challenging on nearly every page and is shot through
with brilliant aphorisms and insights. In the end, Camus rejects suicide: the Absurd
must not be evaded either by religion (“philosophical suicide”) or by
annihilation (“physical suicide”); the task of living should not merely be
accepted, it must be embraced.
The Rebel (1951) – Camus considered this
work a continuation of the critical and philosophical investigation of the
Absurd that he began with The Myth of Sisyphus. Only this time his
concern is not the ethics of suicide, but the problem of murder. After
introducing the view that an authentic life inevitably involves some form of
conscientious moral revolt, he ends up arguing that only in rare, and in very
narrowly defined, instances can political violence be morally justified. Camus’
critique of revolutionary violence and terror in this work, and particularly
his caustic assessment of Marxism-Leninism (which he accused of sacrificing
innocent lives on the altar of History), touched nerves throughout Europe and
led to his celebrated feud with Sartre and other French leftists.
Resistance, Rebellion, and Death (1957)
– This posthumous collection is of interest to students of Camus mainly because
it brings together an unusual assortment of his non-fiction writings on a wide
range of topics, from art and politics to the advantages of pessimism and the
virtues (from a non-believer’s standpoint) of Christianity. Of special interest
are two pieces that helped secure Camus’ worldwide reputation as a voice of
liberty: “Letters to a German Friend” (a set of four letters originally written
during the Nazi Occupation) and “Reflections on the Guillotine” (a denunciation
of the death penalty cited for special mention by the Nobel committee and
eventually revised and re-published as a companion essay to go with fellow
death-penalty opponent Arthur Koestler’s “Reflections on Hanging”).
Philosophy
“More a writer than a philosopher.”
(Assessment penciled on Camus’ dissertation by
his dissertation adviser.)
To re-emphasize a point made earlier, Camus
considered himself first and foremost a writer (un ecrivain).
And at various times in his career he also accepted the labels journalist,
humanist, novelist, and even moralist. However, he apparently
never felt comfortable identifying himself as a philosopher – a term
he seems to have associated with rigorous academic training, systematic
thinking, logical consistency, and a coherent, carefully defined doctrine or
body of ideas.
This is not to suggest that Camus lacked ideas or
to say that his thought cannot be considered a personal philosophy. It
is simply to point out that he was not a systematic, or even a notably
disciplined, thinker and that, unlike Heidegger
and Sartre, for example, he
showed very little interest in metaphysics and ontology (which seems to be one
of the reasons he consistently denied that he was an existentialist). In short,
he was not much given to speculative philosophy or any kind of abstract
theorizing. His thought is instead nearly always related to current events
(e.g., the Spanish War, revolt in Algeria) and is consistently grounded in
down-to-earth moral and political reality.
Themes and Ideas
Regardless of whether he is producing drama,
fiction, or non-fiction, Camus in his mature writings nearly always takes up
and re-explores the same basic philosophical issues. These recurrent topoi
constitute the key components of his thought. They include themes like the
Absurd, alienation, suicide, and rebellion that almost automatically come to
mind whenever his name is mentioned. Hence any summary of his place in modern
philosophy would be incomplete without at least a brief discussion of these
ideas and how they fit together to form a distinctive and original world-view.
Even readers not closely acquainted with Camus’
works are aware of his reputation as the philosophical expositor, anatomist, and
poet-apostle of the absurd. Indeed as even sit-com writers and stand-up comics
apparently understand (odd fact: Camus has been used to explain episodes of Seinfeld
and The Simpsons), it is largely through the thought and writings of
the French-Algerian author that the concept of absurdity has become a part not
only of world literature and twentieth-century philosophy, but of modern
popular culture as well.
What then is meant by the notion of the absurd?
Contrary to the view conveyed by popular culture, the absurd, (at least in
Camus’ terms) does not simply refer to some vague perception that modern life
is fraught with paradoxes, incongruities, and intellectual confusion. Instead,
as he himself emphasizes and tries to make clear, the absurd expresses a fundamental
disharmony, a tragic incompatibility, in our existence. In effect, he argues
that the absurd is the product of a collision or confrontation between our
human desire for order, meaning, and purpose in life and the blank, indifferent
“silence of the universe.” (“The absurd is not in man nor in the world,” Camus
explains, “but in their presence together it is the only bond uniting them.”)
So here we are: poor creatures desperately
seeking hope and meaning in a hopeless, meaningless world. Sartre, in his
essay-review of The Stranger provides an additional gloss on the idea:
“The absurd, to be sure, resides neither in man nor in the world, if you
consider each separately. But since man’s dominant characteristic is ‘being in
the world,’ the absurd is, in the end, an inseparable part of the human
condition.” The absurd, then, presents itself in the form of an existential
opposition. It arises from the human demand for clarity and transcendence on
the one hand and a cosmos that offers nothing of the kind on the other. Such is
our fate: we inhabit a world that is indifferent to our sufferings and deaf to
our protests.
In Camus’ view there are three possible
philosophical responses to this predicament. Two of these he condemns as
evasions; the other he puts forward as a proper solution.
Our first choice is blunt and simple: physical
suicide. If we decide that a life without some essential purpose or meaning is
not worth living, we can simply choose to kill ourselves. Camus rejects this
choice as cowardly. In his terms it is a repudiation or renunciation of life,
not a true revolt.
Choice two is the religious solution of positing
a transcendent world of solace and meaning beyond the Absurd. Camus calls this
solution “philosophical suicide” and rejects it as transparently evasive and
fraudulent. To adopt a supernatural solution to the problem of the absurd (for
example, through some type of mysticism or leap of faith) is to annihilate
reason, which in Camus’ view is as fatal and self-destructive as physical
suicide. In effect, instead of removing himself from the absurd confrontation
of self and world like the physical suicide, the religious believer simply
removes the offending world, replacing it, via a kind of metaphysical
abracadabra, with a more agreeable alternative.
Choice three (in Camus’ view the only authentic
and valid solution) is simply to accept absurdity, or better yet to embrace it,
and to continue living. Since the absurd in his view is an unavoidable, indeed
defining, characteristic of the human condition, the only proper response to it
is full, unflinching, courageous acceptance. Life, he says, can “be lived all
the better if it has no meaning.”
The example par excellence of this option of
spiritual courage and metaphysical revolt is the mythical Sisyphus of Camus’
philosophical essay. Doomed to eternal labor at his rock, fully conscious of
the essential hopelessness of his plight, Sisyphus nevertheless pushes on. In
doing so he becomes for Camus a superb icon of the spirit of revolt and of the
human condition. To rise each day to fight a battle you know you cannot win,
and to do this with wit, grace, compassion for others, and even a sense of
mission, is to face the Absurd in a spirit of true heroism.
Over the course of his career, Camus examines the
Absurd from multiple perspectives and through the eyes of many different
characters – from the mad Caligula, who is obsessed with the problem, to the
strangely aloof and yet simultaneously self-absorbed Mersault, who seems
indifferent to it even as he exemplifies and is finally victimized by it. In The
Myth of Sisyphus Camus traces it in specific characters of legend and
literature (Don Juan, Ivan Karamazov) and also in certain character types (the
Actor, the Conqueror), all of whom may be understood as in some way a version
or manifestation of Sisyphus, the archetypal absurd hero.
Guilt and Innocence
Throughout his writing career, Camus showed a
deep interest in questions of guilt and innocence. Once again Mersault in The
Stranger provides a striking example. Is he legally innocent of the murder
he is charged with? Or is he technically guilty? On the one hand, there seems
to have been no conscious intention behind his action. Indeed the killing takes
place almost as if by accident, with Mersault in a kind of absent-minded daze,
distracted by the sun. From this point of view, his crime seems surreal and his
trial and subsequent conviction a travesty. On the other hand, it is hard for
the reader not to share the view of other characters in the novel, especially
Mersault’s accusers, witnesses, and jury, in whose eyes he seems to be a
seriously defective human being – a kind of hollow man at best; at worst a
monster of self-centeredness and insularity. That the character has evoked such
a wide range of responses from critics and readers – from sympathy to horror –
is a tribute to the psychological complexity and subtlety of Camus’ portrait.
Camus’ brilliantly crafted final novel, The
Fall, continues his keen interest in the theme of guilt, this time via a
narrator who is virtually obsessed with it. The significantly named
Jean-Baptiste Clamence (a voice in the wilderness calling for universal
clemency and forgiveness) is tortured by guilt in the wake of a seemingly
casual incident. While strolling home one drizzly November evening, he shows
little concern and almost no emotional reaction at all to the suicidal plunge
of a young woman into the Seine. But afterwards the incident begins to gnaw at
him, and eventually he comes to view his inaction as typical of a long pattern
of personal vanity and as a colossal failure of human sympathy on his part.
Wracked by remorse and self-loathing, he gradually descends into a figurative
hell. Formerly an attorney, he is now a self-described “judge-penitent” (a
combination sinner, tempter, prosecutor, and father-confessor), who shows up
each night at his local haunt, a sailor’s bar near Amsterdam’s red light
district, where, somewhat in the manner of Coleridge’s Ancient Mariner, he
recounts his story to whoever will hear it. In the final sections of the novel,
amid distinctly Christian imagery and symbolism, he declares his crucial
insight that, despite our pretensions to righteousness, everyone is guilty.
Hence no human being has the right to pass final moral judgment on another.
In a final twist, Clamence asserts that his acid
self-portrait is also a mirror for his contemporaries. Hence his confession is
also an accusation – not only of his nameless companion (who serves as the mute
auditor for his monologue) but ultimately of the hypocrite lecteur as
well.
Existentialism
Camus is often classified as an existentialist
writer, and it is easy to see why. Affinities with Kierkegaard and Sartre are
patent. He shares with these philosophers (and with the other major writers in
the existentialist tradition, from Augustine and Pascal to Dostoyevsky and
Nietzsche) a habitual and intense interest in the active human psyche, in the
life of conscience or spirit as it is actually experienced and lived. Like
these writers, he aims at nothing less than a thorough, candid exegesis of the
human condition, and like them he exhibits not just a philosophical attraction
but also a personal commitment to such values as individualism, free choice,
inner strength, authenticity, personal responsibility, and self-determination.
On the other hand, besides his personal rejection
of the label, there appear to be solid reasons for challenging the claim that
Camus is an existentialist. For one thing, it is noteworthy that he never
showed much interest in (indeed he largely avoided) metaphysical and
ontological questions (the philosophical raison d’etre and bread and
butter of Heidegger and Sartre). Of course there is no rule that says an
existentialist must be a metaphysician. However, Camus’ seeming aversion to
technical philosophical discussion does suggest one way in which he distanced
himself from contemporary existentialist thought.
Works
Novels
* The Stranger (L'Étranger, often
translated as The Outsider) (1942)
* The Plague (La Peste) (1947)
* The Fall (La Chute) (1956)
* A Happy Death (La Mort heureuse)
(written 1936–1938, published posthumously 1971)
* The First Man (Le premier homme)
(incomplete, published posthumously 1995)
Short stories
* Exile and the Kingdom (L'exil et
le royaume) (collection) (1957)
"The Adulterous Woman"
("La Femme adultère")
"The Renegade or a Confused
Spirit" ("Le Renégat ou un esprit confus")
"The Silent Men"
("Les Muets")
"The Guest"
("L'Hôte")
"Jonas or the Artist at
Work" ("Jonas ou l’artiste au travail")
"The Growing Stone"
("La Pierre qui pousse")
Non-fiction books
* Christian Metaphysics and
Neoplatonism (1935)
* Betwixt and Between (L'envers et
l'endroit, also translated as The Wrong Side and the Right Side) (Collection,
1937) * Nuptials (Noces) (1938)
* The Myth of Sisyphus (Le Mythe de
Sisyphe) (1942)
* The Rebel (L'Homme révolté)
(1951)
* Notebooks 1935–1942 (Carnets, mai
1935 — fevrier 1942) (1962)
* Notebooks 1943–1951 (1965) *
Notebooks 1951–1959 (2008) Published as "Carnets Tome III : Mars 1951 –
December 1959" (1989)
Plays
* Caligula (performed 1945, written
1938)
* Requiem for a Nun (Requiem pour une
nonne, adapted from William Faulkner's novel by the same name) (1956)
* The Misunderstanding (Le
Malentendu) (1944)
* The State of Siege (L' Etat de
Siege) (1948)
* The Just Assassins (Les Justes)
(1949)
* The Possessed (Les Possédés,
adapted from Fyodor Dostoyevsky's novel by the same name) (1959)
Essays
* Create Dangerously (Essay on
Realism and Artistic Creation) (1957)
* The Ancient Greek Tragedy
(Parnassos lecture in Greece) (1956)
* The Crisis of Man (Lecture at
Columbia University) (1946)
* Why Spain? (Essay for the
theatrical play L' Etat de Siege) (1948)
* Reflections on the Guillotine
(Réflexions sur la guillotine) (Extended essay, 1957)
* Neither Victims Nor Executioners
(Combat) (1946)
Collected essays
* Resistance, Rebellion, and Death
(1961) – a collection of essays selected by the author.
* Lyrical and Critical Essays
(1970)
* Youthful Writings (1976)
* Between Hell and Reason: Essays
from the Resistance Newspaper "Combat", 1944–1947 (1991)
* Camus at "Combat":
Writing 1944–1947 (2005)
Albert Camus one of the most
influential writers of twentieth century stands tall like a skyscraper touching
the sky. The Nobel Prize winning author,
playwright and philosopher was considered one of the prime pillars of modern
literature. From adolescent years I was
exposed to Jean-Paul Sartre, Franz Kafka and of course Albert Camus through the
universal literary analysis in my mother tongue. The essays which merits
critical acclaim was always a sumptuous dish on a silver platter.
It gives me immense satisfaction
having found a place for Albert Camus in JOHNNY’S BLOG.
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
Subscribe to Post Comments [Atom]
<< Home